Friday, May 2, 2025

To hell with William James (part 1)

 


Was William James really this crazy? Dude!

Can faith ever be rational? For instance, religious faith.

Yes, faith—especially religious faith—can be rational, depending on how we define both "faith" and "rationality."

1. Faith as Trust vs. Faith as Belief Without Evidence

If "faith" means trust in something or someone based on prior experience or partial evidence (e.g., trusting a friend or a tradition), then it can be rational in the same way that inductive reasoning or personal reliance is rational.

However, if faith means believing without evidence, or even in spite of evidence, then it's harder to classify as rational in the strict philosophical sense—though it might still be existentially or pragmatically meaningful.


2. Types of Rationality

  • Epistemic Rationality (concerned with truth and evidence): Religious faith often struggles here unless it is supported by arguments, experience, or internal coherence.

  • Pragmatic Rationality (concerned with what works or benefits us): Faith can be rational in this sense if it provides meaning, moral guidance, or psychological stability.

  • Moral or Existential Rationality: For someone asking, "How should I live?", faith may provide a coherent structure that supports their values and commitments—even if it doesn’t meet scientific standards of proof.


3. Philosophical Perspectives

  • William James ("The Will to Believe"): Argued that in certain cases (like religious belief), it’s rational to commit to a belief without full evidence if the decision is momentous, forced, and not decidable on intellectual grounds alone.

  • Alvin Plantinga: Developed the idea that belief in God can be properly basic—not inferred from other beliefs, but grounded in a way that is still rational (like belief in other minds or the external world).

  • Pascal's Wager: A pragmatic argument for faith, suggesting that believing in God is the better "bet" given the possible outcomes.


Summary:

Religious faith can be rational depending on context:

  • Yes, if it’s trust based on lived experience, tradition, or existential coherence.

  • No, if it means blind belief against all reason or evidence.

Would you like to explore how different religions or philosophies interpret the relationship between faith and reason?


Can you explain the position of William James in more detail?
Absolutely. William James's defense of religious faith is laid out most clearly in his essay “The Will to Believe” (1896). His position is a nuanced and pragmatic response to the question of whether it is ever rational—or even permissible—to believe something without conclusive evidence, especially in matters like religion.

🔍 Core Problem James Is Addressing

James is responding to critics like W.K. Clifford, who famously argued:

“It is wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence.”

Clifford’s position reflects a strict evidentialist view: belief must always be grounded in sufficient empirical evidence. James thinks this is too rigid and misunderstands how human beings actually operate—especially in moral, personal, and religious life.


📌 James’s Central Argument: The “Will to Believe” Doctrine

James argues that it is rationally permissible to believe in some cases without sufficient evidencewhen certain conditions are met.

He outlines three conditions under which belief without sufficient evidence is justified:

  1. The option must be live: It’s a real possibility for the person; they could seriously choose either side.

  2. The option must be forced: You must choose; not choosing is itself a kind of choice.

  3. The option must be momentous: It’s significant and potentially life-changing.

➡️ Religion, for many, fits all three:

  • Live: People are genuinely torn between belief and disbelief.

  • Forced: You can’t suspend judgment forever—you live as if one view is true.

  • Momentous: The implications for how you live, love, and die are profound.


🧠 Why Belief Can Come Before Evidence

James argues that in some domains (like religion), waiting for complete evidence is not neutral—it may actually close off the very experience that could have confirmed the belief. In other words:

“A rule of thinking which would absolutely prevent me from acknowledging certain kinds of truth if those truths were really there, would be an irrational rule.”

For James, belief can sometimes be the precondition for discovering truth. For instance, love, friendship, trust—all often require initial commitment without certainty, which then creates the conditions for verification.


✝️ Application to Religious Faith

In religious belief, James says it may be rationally permissible—even necessary—to believe without proof, because:

  • The truth may only be accessible through the commitment itself.

  • Waiting for proof may exclude one from transformative experiences.

  • Some truths are only “caught” through action, not observed dispassionately.


🧩 In Summary:

William James justifies faith without evidence when:

  • The belief is liveforced, and momentous;

  • The belief involves truths that are practically or existentially important;

  • The act of believing is itself part of how such truths become known.

He’s not saying you should believe everything without evidence—but rather that in some human situations, the demand for certainty is unrealistic, and faith is a rational risk.

Would you like a contrast with Clifford’s evidentialism or Plantinga’s more modern take?


Yes, with Clifford.

Great. Let’s compare William James and W.K. Clifford side by side, as their disagreement goes to the heart of whether religious faith (or any belief) can be rational without full evidence.


🔴 W.K. Clifford: The Ethics of Belief (1877)

🔒 Key Thesis:

“It is wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence.”

Clifford treats belief as a moral responsibility. For him, believing something on inadequate evidence is not just intellectually lazy—it’s ethically wrong. This is because:

  • Beliefs lead to actions, and actions affect others.

  • Holding unjustified beliefs encourages credulity and damages society’s shared epistemic norms.

  • Even if the belief is harmless or turns out to be true, it was still wrong to believe it without sufficient reason.

🔍 Famous Example:

Clifford tells a story of a shipowner who convinces himself (without proper inspection) that his ship is seaworthy. It sinks, and people die. Even if the ship had not sunk, Clifford says the owner’s belief was still morally irresponsible because it was formed irresponsibly.

🧠 Clifford’s View on Religion:

Clifford would argue that religious faith without empirical evidence is intellectually and ethically dangerous. It may foster dogma, superstition, and tribalism. The stakes are high, so only evidence-based belief is acceptable.


🔵 William James: The Will to Believe (1896)

✅ Key Thesis:

“Our passional nature not only lawfully may, but must decide an option between propositions, whenever it is a genuine option that cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual grounds.”

James thinks Clifford’s standard is too strict, and unrealistic in many of life’s most important situations—like love, morality, and religion.

  • Sometimes waiting for complete evidence means losing the opportunity to experience the truth.

  • Belief is sometimes the door to knowledge, not just its result (e.g., trusting someone, or loving someone before knowing they love you back).

  • In areas where science cannot decide, and where the choice is forced and momentous, faith is not only permissible—it’s rational.


⚖️ Core Differences

CategoryCliffordJames
Moral stance on beliefBelieving without sufficient evidence is unethicalBelief without evidence can be justified in special cases
View of evidenceOnly empirical or demonstrable evidence justifies beliefIn “genuine options,” emotions and commitments can justify belief
View of religionFaith is intellectually irresponsible without proofFaith can be rational and even necessary for discovering religious truth
EpistemologyEvidentialist: truth comes before beliefPragmatist: belief can help us find the truth
Belief and actionBeliefs must be tightly policed because they affect othersAction often requires belief before certainty is possible

🧩 Summary

  • CliffordBelief without evidence is always wrong, even if harmless or true.

  • JamesBelief without evidence can be right—if the situation demands a leap and evidence is not available.

Clifford gives us the guardrails of rationality. James gives us the human flexibility needed to live a meaningful life in a world where some truths can't wait for proof.

Would you like to explore how these ideas show up in real-life choices or debates today (like science vs. religion, or politics)?

 

No comments:

Post a Comment